Ethics of Democracy
Part 5,
Politico-Economic Principles
Chap. 1, Political Economy a Science of Tendencies
The basic
principle of Economics, of the art of ordering the social relations of
mankind, may then be summed up in the one word Justice.
- Lewis H. Berens,
in "Toward the Light"
Are there no
slaves to-day? While we sit here at play,
Have we no
brothers in adversity?
None sorry nor
oppressed, who without hope or rest
Must toil and have
no pleasure in their toil?
These are your
slaves and mine. Where is the right divine
Of idlers to
encumber God's good soil?
There is no man
alive, however he may strive,
Allowed to own the
work of his own hands.
Landlords and
water lords at all the roads and fords,
Taking their toll,
imposing their commands.
- Bliss Carman
Not
ermine clad, nor clothed in state,
Their title deeds
not yet made plain;
But waking early,
toiling late,
The heirs of all
the earth remain.
Some day, by laws
as fixed and fair
As guide the
planets in their sweep,
The children of
each outcast heir
The harvest fruits
of time shall reap.
Some day without a
trumpet's call,
This news shall
o'er the earth be blown:
The heritage comes
back to all;
The myriad
monarchs take their own.
- Thomas Wentworth
Higginson
Grimly
the same spirit looks into the law of Property, and accuses men of
driving a trade in the great boundless Providence which had given the
air, the water, and the land to men to use and not to fence in and
monopolize. ("The Times.") I cannot occupy the bleakest
crag of the White Hills or the Allegheny Range, but some man or
corporation steps up to me to show me that it is his. ("The
Conservative.") Touch
any wood, or field, or house lot on your peril; but you may come and
work in ours for us, and we will give you a piece of bread. ("The
Conservative.") Of
course, whilst another man has no land, my title to mine, your title to
yours, is at once vitiated. ("Man the
Reformer.")
- Ralph Waldo Emerson
Properly speaking,
the land belongs to these two: To the Almighty God; and to all his
Children of Men that have ever worked well on it, or that shall ever
work well on it. No generation of men can or could, with never such
solemnity and effort, sell Land on any other principle: it is not the
property of any generation.
- Thomas Carlyle, in
"Past and Present,"
Book III, Chapter VIII.
To any plain
understanding the right of property is very simple. It is the right of
man to possess, enjoy, and transfer, the substance and use of whatever
he has himself created. This title is good against the world; and it is
the sole and only title by which a valid right of absolute private
property can possibly vest. But no man can plead any such title to a
right of property in the substance of the soil.
- James Fintan Lalor, in "The
Irish Felon," July 8, 1848.
It is easy to persuade the masses that the good things of this
world are unjustly divided - especially when it happens to be the
exact truth.
- Froude's "Caesar."
To affirm that a
man can rightfully claim exclusive ownership in his own labor when
embodied in material things, is to deny that any one can rightfully
claim exclusive ownership in land. -("Progress and
Poverty," Book VII, Ch. I.)
So far from the recognition of private property in land being necessary
to the proper use of land, the contrary is the case. Treating land as
private property stands in the way of its proper use. Were land treated
as public property it would be used and improved as soon as there was
need for its use or improvement, but being treated as private property,
the individual owner is permitted to prevent others from using or
improving what he cannot or will not use or improve himself.
-(Same, Book VIII, Ch. I.) We
should satisfy the law of justice, we should meet all economic
requirements, by at one stroke abolishing all private titles, declaring
all land public property, and letting it out to the highest bidders in
lots to suit, under such conditions as would sacredly guard the private
right to improvements.... But such a plan, though perfectly feasible,
does not seem to me the best. Or rather I propose to accomplish the
same thing in a simpler, easier, and quieter way, than that of formally
confiscating all the land and formally letting it out to the highest
bidders.... We already take some rent in taxation. We have only to make
some changes in our modes of taxation to take it all. What I,
therefore, propose... is - to appropriate rent by taxation.... Now,
inasmuch as the taxation of rent, or land values, must necessarily be
increased just as we abolish other taxes, we may put the proposition
into practical form by proposing - to
abolish all taxation save that upon land values.
(Same, Book VIII, Ch. II.)
- Henry George
Hither,
ye blind, from your futile banding!
Know the rights
and the rights are won.
Wrong shall die
with the understanding,
One truth clear,
and the work is done.
Nature is higher
than Progress or Knowledge
Whose need is
ninety enslaved for ten.
My word shall
stand against mart and college:
The planet belongs
to its living men!
- "Liberty," by John
Boyle O'Reilly
|
Saving Communities
Bringing
prosperity through freedom, equality, local
autonomy and respect for the commons.
|
The Ethics of Democracy
by Louis F. Post
Part 5,
Politico-Economic Principles
Chapter 1, Political Economy a Science of Tendencies
TO the billowy sea of economic phenomena there is a mean
level, analogous to that of the terrestrial ocean, The mean level of
the ocean is what its level would be if there were no tides nor waves.
It is the level at which the tides equilibrate, and toward which wave
crests fall and wave hollows rise. This common level to which all
undulations tend, affords a stable basis for calculation. No one would
think of objecting to it because the waves throw up higher crests and
hollow out lower depressions. Nor would anyone for that reason
discredit generalizations that depend upon it. No one, for instance,
would set up the fact that some ocean waves rise higher than the Hudson
river, to discredit the conclusion that the Hudson river must empty
into the ocean because its mean level is higher than the ocean's. Yet,
with reference to political economy, in which the mean level of the
ocean has its perfect analogue, just such objections are gravely
raised.
Political economy, which is simply the social economy of mankind as
distinguished from the personal economy of individual men, is a science
of tendencies. So understood, it is an exact science. Just as the mean
level of the ocean may be exactly ascertained, though the waves rise
and fall in a way to defy calculation, so the mean level of economic
undulations may be exactly determined, notwithstanding the number,
variety, uncertainty and complexity of individual transactions. But
there are students of economic science who ignore this, and reject
sound economic generalizations, even such as would appear to the
untutored to be axiomatic, for no better reason than that they are
contradicted by some transitory economic phenomenon. It is as if the
greater height of a particular wave, or the deeper depression between
two waves, were cited to show that the mean level of the ocean is a
mere assumption which facts disprove.
A familiar example of this species of perversity is the denial by some
economists that cost of production determines the value of products.
Particular products are instanced, the value of which is conceded or
shown to be very much above or below the cost of their production, and
also of their reproduction. This seems to invalidate the
generalization, but it does nothing of the kind. Such instances, like
the waves of the ocean, are only undulations. At the mean level of
economic phenomena, the axiomatic truth still holds good, that cost of
production determines the value of products. Trade being unobstructed,
no kind of production can be carried on long with the value of products
either above or below their cost. If their value remained below cost,
their production would cease for lack of remuneration; if it staid
above cost, competition would set in and draw off purchasers. Whatever
the undulations in value may at any time happen to be, the cost of
products does in general determine the value of products.
Another example of the disposition to discredit sound general
principles in political economy by reference to particular economic
undulations, is connected with the incidence of taxes. When levied upon
a product of current labor, taxes are found to enhance the price of the
product, thus shifting the burden of the taxation from the maker or
seller of the taxed product to its last buyer or consumer. The general
principle consequently inferred is that taxes on labor products are
borne by consumers. But this generalization is often denied because
there are instances in conflict with it; as for example, that stamp
taxes on proprietary medicines are not always added to the price. Yet
that denial is only an instance of disputing the mean level by
measuring the altitude of a wave crest. A one-cent stamp tax upon a
dollar bottle of medicine might not be added to the price. But this
proves nothing except that in that instance the tax is too small to
produce its normal effect. A dollar stamp tax upon a dollar bottle of
medicine would certainly express itself in the price. So would a tax
very much less than a dollar. And if the proprietary medicine happened
to be subject to keen competition, even so small a tax as one cent
would be shifted to the final buyer.
Any tax upon products, however light it may be, has a tendency to
increase their price, just as any pressure upon a wall has a tendency
to topple it over. Whether the tendency produces its natural effect
must depend in the one case, as in the other, upon such circumstances
as its own persistence and the resistance it meets. When a tax is high
enough on products to leave the producers no remuneration for their
work, the price must go up or production must cease. Men will not
produce for nothing. Though some taxes on some products may not for
some time be shifted to consumers through higher prices, it is
nevertheless absolutely true that at the mean level of economic
phenomena, taxes on current production are shifted from producers to
consumers, just as in the specific instances of telegraph tolls and
express charges, during the war with Spain, the one-cent internal
revenue stamp tax was shifted from the corporations to the persons who
sent messages and shipped packages.
Still another sound generalization, probably the most important in the
whole range of political economy, is often disputed with no better
reason that that it is contradicted by some undulation or other upon
the restless surface of economic phenomena. It is the simple but
exceedingly luminous truth that demand for consumption determines the
direction in which labor will be expended in production. If, for
illustration, consumers increase the demand for bread and lessen the
demand for beef, producers will quickly respond by diverting some of
their energies from beef-making to bread-making. Especially impressive
illustrations of this great economic truth are observable when some
fashionable product, such as hoopskirts once were, goes out of fashion.
The expenditure of labor in the direction of producing that article
ceases at once. Cessation of demand causes cessation of production. On
the other hand, when a new product comes into general use, as the
bicycle or the automobile, labor turns in the direction of producing it
in quantity and quality to meet the demand of consumers. These
instances exemplify in a marked way the principle that demand for
consumption determines the direction of labor in production. The same
principle operates when the change is not so marked. Any variation in
demand for consumption tends to cause a corresponding variation of the
direction in which labor is expended in production.
But this almost obtrusive principle is often denied or ignored, because
in some industries the producer has had to create a demand for his
products. From that fact it is argued that, in those cases at any rate,
the direction of production has determined the demand for consumption,
and the principle been thus reversed.
Such cases do not rise to the dignity even of exceptions to a general
rule. Though the producer does solicit consumers, his production is on
the whole only in response to demand, even though he has himself
stimulated the demand into activity. It was many years after some
bicycle manufacturers began to whip up demands for the "wheel" that a
great demand set in; but it is evident that upon the mean level of
economic phenomena it is demand for bicycles that turns labor to their
production or away from it, 'and not their production that makes
consumers demand them, nor a decline in production that causes demand
to fall off.
It is similar with the accumulation of goods in stores in advance of
the actual demand for them. Though this seems like an instance of
production causing demand, it is in fact a splendid instance of demand
causing production. The fact that particular goods are produced in
advance of particular demand is immaterial. That is only an undulation
on the surface of economic phenomena. They are produced in reliance
upon a demand which experience has proved to be constant. Particular
goods in great quantity and variety are continually produced to Chicago
in advance of the particular demands of Chicago consumers. But this is
not because production determines demand. It is because Chicago is
known to be a center to which consumers come to satisfy their demands.
It is demand for goods at Chicago that brings goods there; not their
being there that makes the demand. Goods are never produced in great
quantity and variety to prairie hamlets in expectation of creating a
demand for them there. Since the usual demand at hamlets is for a few
goods of meager variety, only a few simple goods are produced to the
hamlet. It is the character of the constant demand for consumption that
determines the production, on the one hand, of great storehouses of
goods to a Chicago, and on the other of small supplies to cross-roads
stores.
That demand for consumption determines the direction in which labor
will be expended in production is an indisputable truth. Any instance
which apparently contradicts it is either no contradiction at all, or
is analogous to a rolling wave that rises above or sinks below the mean
level of the ocean.
The absorption of the pecuniary benefits of material progress by land
values, is yet another mean level principle of political economy to
which undulatory economists object When and where land is monopolized,
the pecuniary benefits of local progress must add to local land values;
and ultimately local land values will altogether measure these benefits
as compared with the benefits other localities have to offer. Instances
of the truth of this principle are abundant, but no experimental
demonstration is really needed. Any celestial visitor who had never
heard of political economy, of land, of land values, or of material
progress, but whose logical machinery was intact, could reason it out.
Given a community in which all the land is monopolized, so that no one
can enjoy any of the benefits of living or working there without the
consent of some local landowner, obtainable only at a price in
competition, and it is inevitable that any advantages which that
community has to offer will be charged for by the landowners in higher
rents and higher selling prices for land, and that ultimately this
charge will come to equal the pecuniary advantages of living or working
in that community. This principle is so evidently universal that it
must apply not only to a little community but to the whole world. Yet
it also is a principle which has been discredited in some minds by some
economic undulation or other.
Such economic phenomena as the fall of farm land values in old England
and New England are frequently but quite mistakenly referred to as
having completely done away with the principle. While it may be true
that these values have fallen as compared with what they were a few
years ago, it is not true that they have fallen as compared with what
they were 300 years ago. We therefore mistake a fluctuation for a
tendency, an undulation for the mean level, if we assume that these
temporary depressions of value in recent years are in contradiction of
the general principle that land values absorb the pecuniary benefits of
progress.
Moreover, and this is the more important consideration, though some
land values have fallen in some places, other land values have risen in
other places. Before the English and New England farm-land values
declined, Dakota and Manitoba farm-land values were at zero. These have
risen as the others have fallen, and manifestly in greater degree.
Likewise, as farm-land values have fallen or remained stationary, town
values and mine values have risen enormously. The test of the principle
is not whether land values for certain purposes or in certain places
have risen or fallen. That test would determine nothing but
undulations. The real question is whether land values have risen or
fallen on the whole. That is where the mean level lies. In fact land
values as a whole have risen wonderfully within the past fifty years.
There is but little land now in all the civilized world which is not
worth as much as it was half a century ago; and there is much that has
multiplied in value a hundred, a thousand, or ten thousand
fold.
Even if land values have not yet absorbed all the pecuniary benefits of
civilization, their tendency to do so is manifest; and in so far as
they fall short of it, the explanation lies plainly in the fact that
the monopolization of the earth is not yet complete.
One very remarkable respect in which economists ignore the mean level
of political economy, while they concentrate attention upon
undulations, remains to be considered. It is, however, more interesting
than important; in which respect it differs from the other instances. I
refer to their caviling over what is called "unearned
increment."
The term may not be felicitous, but it roughly describes increase in
land values. Since land values, unlike most other values, tend to
increase with advancing civilization, the increase is referred to as an
"increment"; and as they are not earned, wherein also they differ from
other values, the increment is called "unearned." Hence, "unearned
increment." It would be futile now, and is altogether needless, to
quarrel with the infelicity of this term. For all practical purposes it
is good enough; and it has the advantage of directing attention to the
fact that owners of land get a value which they do not earn. The
injustice of that is instinctively recognized, and has suggested the
propriety of taking the "unearned increment" of land for common use,
upon the theory that "unearned" values are rightly common
property.
So effective is this suggestion, that special pleaders for
land-monopoly are exceedingly cautious about making frontal attacks
upon it. Preferring flank movements, they admit that land does take on
an "unearned increment of value; but they assert that this is
unimportant because other things besides land do the same. And from
that they argue that the "unearned increment" of land cannot fairly be
made a common fund unless all other "unearned increments" are similarly
treated. Supposing that to be impossible or unjust, they snap their
fingers triumphantly and shout, "Check!" or maybe, "Check mate!" Here
is a charming example of undulatory economics.
One class of illustrations on which these special pleaders dwell,
comprises such unique things as rare coins and old books and pictures.
But the increasing value of such objects has no more relation to
political economy than your grandmother's portrait has to household
economy or her wedding slippers to the shoe trade.
Another favorite illustration is the diamond found in the street. The
finder does not labor; for, though there is exertion in his stooping to
pick up the diamond, it is wholly disproportionate to the value of the
stone. This illustration is quite pointless. There is no "increment" of
value, none whatever, to a lost diamond which has been found. Its value
is no more after the finding than before the losing. Such value as the
finder acquires is only that which the loser lost. The finder truly
comes into possession of value without earning it; but the loser owns
that value, and if he claims it the law will justly restore it to
him.
A far better illustration of the same point was furnished some years
ago by a newspaper report of a Western lawsuit. On a certain Western
farm, according to this report, an aerolite dropped one night and sunk
into the ground. A wayfarer who had seen it fall, dug up the aerolite
and sold it to a college for $250. His labor was so slight, in
comparison with that price, that it may be disregarded for the purposes
of this illustration. The wayfarer, therefore, would appear to have
been the owner of $250 of "unearned increment" to aerolite. But not so.
Before the payment the owner of the farm where the aerolite had fallen
put in an appearance, claiming the money; and the courts decided that
it belonged to him and not to the wayfarer. They reasoned, quite
correctly, that the aerolite became part of the land as soon as it
fell. So this $250, instead of being an "unearned increment" to
aerolite, was an "unearned increment" to land. It is so with nearly all
"unearned increments." At the mean level of economic phenomena they
attach to land.
As with the Western aerolite so would it be with diamonds found where
nature had left them. If you find a diamond in its natural state on a
landowner's premises, the value of the diamond is his and not yours. It
is an "unearned increment," not to diamond, but to land. If you found
it upon public land, it would be yours; and as to that particular
stone, you might seem in that case to have acquired an "unearned
increment." But this would be in seeming only. At most it would be an
economic undulation. That the value of a diamond so found is
essentially an "unearned increment" to land may be seen if we suppose,
what would naturally be the case, that it is not a stray stone you have
found, but a diamond deposit. Should you have found this on private
land, the land would rise in value as knowledge of the discovery
spread, until all the "unearned increment" to those diamonds had
attached to the land where they lay. The same thing, with a difference
only as to beneficiaries, would occur if your "find" were upon public
land. You, or some one else, would hasten to acquire private title to
the site of the diamond deposit, and through the land monopoly thus
created would as landlord appropriate all the "unearned increment,"
thereby making it an "unearned increment" to land. The history of
Kimberley tells that story eloquently.
Analyze the "unearned increments" to other things than land, and almost
all of them prove at last to be "unearned increments" to land. All
instances to the contrary (such as the finding of a stray diamond
without an owner, or the increase in value of relics and rarities),
which the most laborious student can discover or the most imaginative
controversialist invent, will prove upon investigation to be to the
mean level of economic phenomena what rolling waves are to the mean
level of the ocean - mere transitory undulations.
Very much of the deferential quarreling among economists might cease
were the fact more clearly recognized that economic phenomena have a
mean level toward which all undulations tend; if it were better
understood, that is, that political economy is a science of tendencies.
In a way, this is recognized. But the recognition is quite perfunctory.
It is, indeed, only verbal, as a glance through almost any book on the
subject will show. Modern text-books in political economy are given
over largely to erecting sectional views of economic undulations. And
this is not so much for the purpose of coming at the mean level in that
needlessly difficult way, as to show that there is no mean level at
all, but only a vast confusion of tossing waves and tumbling billows.
|
Navigation
We Provide
How You Can Help
- Research
- Outreach
- Transcribing Documents
- Donating Money
- Training for Responsibility
Our Constituents
- Public Officials
- Small Businesses
- Family Farms
- Organic Farms
- Vegetarians
- Labor
- Real Estate Leaders
- Innovative Land Speculators
- Homeowners
- Tenants
- Ethnic
Minorities
- Ideological Groups
Fundamental Principles
- Decentralism and Freedom
- Focusing on Local Reform
- Government as Referee
- Government as Public Servant
- Earth as a Commons
- Money as a Common Medium
- Property Derives from Labor
Derivative Issues
- Wealth Concentration
- Corruption
- Bureaucracy
- Authorities
- Privatization
- Centralization
- Globalization and Trade
- Economic Stagnation
- Boom-Bust Cycles
- Development Subsidies
- Sprawl
- Gentrification
- Pollution and Depletion
- Public Services
- Transportation
- Education
- Health Care
- Retirement
- Wages
- Zoning
- Parks
- Shared Services
Blinding Misconceptions
- Orwellian Economics
- Corporate Efficiency
- Democracy vs. Elections
- Big Government Solutions
- Founding Fathers
- Politics of Fear
- Politics of Least Resistance
- Radical vs. Militant
- Left vs. Right
- Common vs. Collective
- Analysis vs. Vilification
- Influence vs. Power
|