The Ethics of Democracy
by Louis F. Post
Part 4, Economic
Tendencies
Chapter 7, The Trust and the Single Tax
A VERY simple illustration of the trust may be imagined
by considering the hack service at almost any commodious railway
station, whether in city or country. I select a particular one for the
sake of being definite. Hackettstown is a New Jersey station on the
Delaware, Lackawanna & Western Railway, where the station yard
is large enough to accommodate many more hacks than are needed. Several
hacks carry passengers between this station yard and any desired place
in the town at the uniform charge of a dime. Were more exacted,
competition would be stimulated. Realizing this possibility, the hack
owners conform voluntarily to what is locally regarded as a fair toll.
The business, therefore, is regulated by competition - if not actual,
yet potential.
Consolidation of these interests might effect economies. If so, the
consolidation would be beneficial to all concerned. Patrons would get
better service and pay lower fares; and if displaced employes were hurt
by it, their misfortune would be due, not to the labor-saving
consolidation of Hackettstown hack interests, but, as is the case with
the introduction of labor-saving machines, to fundamental legal
obstructions to business in general. The consolidation would be nothing
but a union of interests in hacks and horses, a kind of property too
easily produced in abundant quantities to be monopolized. Such unions
are not in themselves harmful. If they were, all economizing devices
would be harmful, and, following Tolstoy, we should have to return to
primitive methods of production.
But note the effect were the railroad company to confer upon those hack
owners exclusive rights to enter the station yard with hacks. As the
station building is so situated with reference to the public highway
that competing hackmen could not satisfy the needs of passengers
without access to the yard, the privileged hack owners would control
the business as a monopoly. Though they still competed with one
another, they would be shielded from the competition of outsiders. What
if they consolidate now? How radical the difference! The consolidated
interests would be more than interests in hacks and horses. They would
comprise exclusive rights of entry into the station yard. And therein
would lie the evil power of this local hack trust. Freed from all fear
of competition, it could make a standard of service to suit itself, and
regulate fares upon the basis of extorting "all the traffic would
bear."
This illustration is so far typical of business in general as to
indicate the point at which the evil of the trust comes in to bedevil
modern industry. That point is not where competitive businesses
combine; it is where competing monopolies come into the combination.
When really powerful trusts are analyzed, their power is found to rest
in some form of monopoly - in some species of privilege. Somewhere in
every evil trust, though not always obvious, there is a consolidation
of exclusive interests analogous to the station yard monopoly of our
illustration.
Mr. Charles M. Schwab recognized this when in his testimony before the
Industrial Commission he affirmed that the steel trust, of which he was
manager, absolutely controls 80 per cent, of the iron ore deposits of
this country, and all the best coking-coal lands known.
Specifically, the monopoly interests upon the consolidation of which
trusts are erected are numerous and various. They consist of such
monopolies as railroad rights of way, pipe-line rights of way, patented
inventions, water privileges, street franchises, mining rights,
terminal sites, and so on into a long catalogue. But most of them may
be properly classified as monopolies of land. Mining rights are
obviously land rights. Railroad and pipeline rights of way, terminal
sites, and the like, are evidently so.
To make land monopoly the mother of trusts, however, it is not
necessary to trace directly to land monopoly every special privilege
that may not obviously spring from that source. The important
consideration is that all monopolies which do not spring from, are
necessarily subordinate to, monopolies of land. A monopoly of iron
mines, for instance, confers control over the iron industry in all its
ramifications, including all its minor monopolies. That control may be
limited by a monopoly of rights of way, and especially of necessary
terminal points for the shipment or delivery of products of the iron
industry. But this makes no difference to the argument, for both
monopolies are monopolies of land. And, if these two land monopolies be
united in one trust, that trust is unconquerable, except by a trust
that monopolizes still more important natural sources of supply or
still more commanding terminal sites.
In yet another, a more subtle and therefore more effective way, evil
trusts are fostered by land monopoly. This is through general
speculation in land. In the hope of profiting by increase in land
prices, every one who can afford to invest buys land where he thinks it
may rise in value. Most of the land so bought is either not used at all
or only partly used. It cannot be easily obtained for use, because it
is held upon speculation at excessive prices. In consequence of this
difficulty, the industrial classes are forced into a glutted labor
market, like cattle into a corral. As all processes of industry depend
upon land, workers of every grade are huddled together begging for some
kind of job. Those that are not actually in the corral are in mortal
fear of getting into it. In these circumstances, the industrial classes
are an easy prey to whoever has a job to give them. To escape the
corral, they accept any terms they can get. They cannot contract in
freedom, for they must buy a chance to live. The question with them is
not one of more or less income, but of life or death. Thus the monopoly
power that trusts acquire from ownership of land is multiplied by the
relative weakness of their landless victims. "The destruction of the
poor is their poverty." And their poverty, as well as the original
power of the trusts, is rooted in, springs from, and is strengthened by
land monopoly.
This monopoly not only strengthens the trusts by weakening the
contracting power of their workmen; it is also the fundamental cause of
the suffering which all classes that eat their bread in the sweat of
their own faces are forced to endure from what seems to them the
"ravages" of labor-saving machinery and other economizing devices. The
only radical remedy, therefore, not only for the evil of the trust but
also for the evil effects of what ought to be an unmixed and universal
good, namely, labor-saving methods, is the abolition of land
monopoly.
This is the comprehensive, because the radical or root remedy, for
industrial maladjustment, which Henry George proposed to apply by what
has come to be known by the name of "the single tax." It was his idea
to continue, in lieu of all other taxes, the tax we already impose upon
the value of land - namely, that part of the real estate tax which is
measured by the value of sites as distinguished from the value of
improvements. To put his proposition in another form, he would abolish
all taxes except the one which is measured solely by land values,
trusting to the resulting increase in the rate of that single tax to
transfer from land monopolists to the public treasury the annual ground
rent, potential as well as actual, of all kinds of land - mines and
city lots as well as agricultural land - each allotment paying in
proportion to its value as mere land, irrespective of the value of its
improvements. By this means land monopoly would be abolished. It would
be abolished in the only way in which land monopoly can be abolished
without reviving it in new forms by turning the state into a monster
landlord of unlimited and virtually irresponsible power. For, while it
would effectually abolish the monopoly of land, the single tax would
preserve private possession under individual occupancy.
If this principle, the principle of the single tax, were fully applied,
land monopoly would evidently be impossible. Vacant city lots would not
be held long for higher prices, if the owner had to pay as heavy a tax
as the owner of improved lots having an equal land value. Farming land
could not be kept out of use by the thriftless or the greedy, nor by
land-grant railroads, if the unimproved were taxed as much as the
improved, the locations being of equal value. The coal and ore mines of
the country could not be monopolized and closed against mining, if coal
land were taxed well up to its market value whether worked or not. In
every direction this tax would put fines upon land monopolists, thereby
discouraging land monopoly and opening to general us all the natural
opportunities which are now closed by owners who expect to reap a
harvest of higher prices in the future.
And while abolishing land monopoly, on the one hand, the single tax
would, on the other, abolish all fines upon production, thereby
releasing the great body of labor from the corral into which it has
been driven, and causing work to bid for men instead of compelling men
to bid for work.
Different kinds of cases might require different modes of applying the
single tax principle. With reference to transportation, when right of
way and mode of operation were inseparable, and even with reference to
some kinds of mines, as gold or silver mines, it might be necessary, in
order to destroy land monopoly as to them, to place them directly under
public management. Where that was true, special modes of applying the
single tax principle might be adopted. But in all probability little
more would be found necessary in actual experience than the fiscal
method of application proposed by Henry George, which, like the single
tax principle itself, is also known as "the single tax." At all events
this method would be efficient in most cases and with the most vital
elements of the problem.
But the question recurs in more concrete form. "How," it is often
asked, "could the single tax benefit the small storekeeper, the small
manufacturer, the small farmer, and the dependent wage-worker?" Since
large farmers, with the advantage of improved and valuable machinery,
can produce at lower cost than the small farmer, could they not drive
him out of business? In like manner, could not the department store
with its vast capital drive out of business the small storekeeper, and
the large factory the small manufacturer? How could the single tax
offset these great advantages of the capitalist farmers' machinery over
the small farmers' rude methods, and those of the large store and
factory over the small one? And with all these small employers out of
the way, why couldn't the large ones make their own terms with wage
workers?
This question assumes, to begin with, that it is desirable to
perpetuate small modes of production, like small farming, small
manufacturing, and small storekeeping, in behalf of producers on a
small scale. That is not necessarily so. In every department of
industry in which production can be carried on with greater economy of
labor on a large scale than on a small scale, it is desirable that
production on the small scale should give way. Whether or not the
single tax would permit department stores, mammoth factories, and
bonanza farming to put an end to small storekeeping, small
manufacturing, and small farming, is therefore beside the question. The
real question is whether the single tax would secure to those who now
keep small stores, manage small factories, do small farming, and those
who work for hire, their just share in the benefits of the
change.
Henry George had no expectation of interfering by the single tax with
normal concentration in production. On the contrary, he expected the
single tax to encourage it. But he expected also that the single tax
would open the way to all who so desired, to be equal partners in
production - equal, that is to say, in proportion to their
contributions of labor. He expected, in other words, that the single
tax would bring about in the field of production on a large scale, a
system of voluntary cooperation; or, to use his own language in "Progress and Poverty,"
that under the single tax "we should reach the ideal of the socialist,
but not through governmental repression."
This ideal would be reached through the radical change in the
distribution of wealth which the single tax would effect. The system,
being of general application, would automatically distribute products
in two funds. The first fund would consist of the distinguishable
earnings of individuals; the second, of the rent or value or premiums
for exceptional natural and communal opportunities for production.
Among individual workers, the first fund would be divided in proportion
to their usefulness; the other fund would go to the community as a
whole. The natural law or social force by which this equitable
distribution would be made, is free competition, which, like air
pressure, so long as it exerts itself not in one direction but in all,
produces equilibrium.
To those who understand the true nature of free competition, and do not
confound it with the monopolistic phenomena of the present day, which
superficial writers mistakenly allude to as "competition," it is
perfectly clear how the result outlined above would come to pass under
the single tax. But there are those who fail to grasp the idea, and I
venture a suggestion.
When it is asked, How would the small farmer, the small manufacturer,
the small storekeeper and the wageworker fare under the single tax,
with the big factory, the bonanza farm and the department store ruling
the roost? might it not be more pertinent to ask, How the department
store, the great factory, and the bonanza farmer would fare, if they
could get no one to work for them? Think a moment of the effect the
single tax would have upon the labor market. Everyone who monopolized
land that other people wanted to use, would have to pay a tax upon it
so nearly approximating its annual value that he could never hope to
recoup the tax unless he used the land to its full capacity. He would
therefore so use it himself, or would relinquish it to some one else.
But land cannot be used on any but a primitive scale without the
employment of men. Men must be employed, no matter how much machinery
there may be. Machinery will not work itself. Consequently, everybody
who owned land would either have to hire enough men to work it to the
full, or give it up to somebody who would. In either case the effect
upon the labor market would be the same, namely, a brisk demand for
labor in all departments and of all grades, a demand that would
constantly exceed the supply. Jobs would be hunting for men, instead of
men hunting for jobs. The inevitable effect of that would be the
disbandment of the army of the unemployed, increase of wages, and the
consequent independence of workmen. Workmen, though hired, would then
have to be treated as industrial equals. They could no longer be
treated as serfs. If they objected to their treatment by one employer,
they could easily find others; and if they objected to being hired by
any employer, they could themselves become cooperative producers on a
large scale, hiring one another.
The way, therefore, in which the single tax would relieve small
producers and dependent wage-workers would be by causing favorable
conditions in two respects. First, by so increasing the effective
demand for labor as to keep it always in excess of the supply; and,
second, by clearing the way for successful voluntary cooperative
organizations among producers.
The one thing to bear in mind with reference to the single tax
principle is that it contemplates the abolition of land monopoly and
the consequent freeing of industry from all monopoly shackles and
trammels. It would accomplish this by making competition free.
Competition being the antithesis of monopoly, to abolish one is to
establish the other. To make competition free, therefore, is to apply
the natural remedy to the ills that flow from monopoly. Now, all the
ills which seem to come from normal production on a large scale are
caused by the same monopolistic circumstances that make the evil trust
possible. To get rid of them, we must adopt the same remedy that is
required for the trust. Free competition must be established.
Whoever will consider what free competition means, will realize the
beneficently progressive character of the effects that would be
produced by the introduction of a principle like that of the single
tax, which is simply an effective method of unshackling competition.
With competition freed and monopoly abolished no one could fail to
secure his equitable share in the benefits of social growth. To all
such the new modes of production which were more prolific and required
less labor, would be welcomed as a boon. It is the operation of the
principle of monopoly, not of free competition, that makes them now a
menace. If the great factory, the department store, capitalistic
farming, or any other normal species of large production is a menace to
any industrial class, it is not because such method is in itself bad,
but because the injured class is divested of its competing power.
Restore that power by abolishing monopoly through making competition
free, and special difficulties of adjustment which now seem insuperable
obstacles, would prove to be the merest shadows in the path. What labor
of all grades needs is not to be helped but to be freed. Being freed,
it would help itself. It can be freed only by abolishing the monopoly
of land, for land is the native element of labor.
By means of the single tax principle the abolition of land monopoly can
be fully accomplished. By means of the single tax method it can be far
advanced. Under this simple land reform, sound in economics and
unassailable in morals, no one could hold any kind of land out of use
without suffering serious and continual loss. Land would have to be
used, and be well used, or be abandoned. There would be no profit in
mere ownership. That goal being reached - indeed, long before it had
been fully reached - trade having meanwhile and by the same method been
freed by the abolition of commercial and industrial taxes, and of
highway obstacles, the benefits of economic improvement would be
generally diffused and the evil spirit of the trust would be exorcised.
With the annual value of special landed advantages applied to common
use and no longer retained by private owners; with taxes on industry
thus made unnecessary, and consequently abolished; with highways freed
from special privilege; with unused land everywhere made freely
accessible, and the barriers of the industrial corral thus broken down;
with demand for productive work thereby made to exceed supply, and
through the free interplay of all the economic forces of consumption
and production perpetually to maintain that excess, - with these
demonstrable effects of the single tax realized, there would be no more
possibility of subjugating labor and monopolizing business with paper
agreements, than of holding back the waters of Niagara with a paper
dam.
|
Navigation
We Provide
How You Can Help
- Research
- Outreach
- Transcribing Documents
- Donating Money
- Training for Responsibility
Our Constituents
- Public Officials
- Small Businesses
- Family Farms
- Organic Farms
- Vegetarians
- Labor
- Real Estate Leaders
- Innovative Land Speculators
- Homeowners
- Tenants
- Ethnic
Minorities
- Ideological Groups
Fundamental Principles
- Decentralism and Freedom
- Focusing on Local Reform
- Government as Referee
- Government as Public Servant
- Earth as a Commons
- Money as a Common Medium
- Property Derives from Labor
Derivative Issues
- Wealth Concentration
- Corruption
- Bureaucracy
- Authorities
- Privatization
- Centralization
- Globalization and Trade
- Economic Stagnation
- Boom-Bust Cycles
- Development Subsidies
- Sprawl
- Gentrification
- Pollution and Depletion
- Public Services
- Transportation
- Education
- Health Care
- Retirement
- Wages
- Zoning
- Parks
- Shared Services
Blinding Misconceptions
- Orwellian Economics
- Corporate Efficiency
- Democracy vs. Elections
- Big Government Solutions
- Founding Fathers
- Politics of Fear
- Politics of Least Resistance
- Radical vs. Militant
- Left vs. Right
- Common vs. Collective
- Analysis vs. Vilification
- Influence vs. Power
|