Ethics of Democracy
Part 5,
Politico-Economic Principles
Chap. 4, The Wages System
The basic
principle of Economics,
of the art of ordering the social relations of mankind, may then be
summed up in the one word Justice.
- Lewis H. Berens,
in "Toward the Light"
Are there no
slaves to-day? While we sit here at play,
Have we no
brothers in adversity?
None sorry nor
oppressed, who without hope or rest
Must toil and have
no pleasure in their toil?
These are your
slaves and mine. Where is the right divine
Of idlers to
encumber God's good soil?
There is no man
alive, however he may strive,
Allowed to own the
work of his own hands.
Landlords and
water lords at all the roads and fords,
Taking their toll,
imposing their commands.
- Bliss Carman
Not
ermine clad, nor clothed in state,
Their title deeds
not yet made plain;
But waking early,
toiling late,
The heirs of all
the earth remain.
Some day, by laws
as fixed and fair
As guide the
planets in their sweep,
The children of
each outcast heir
The harvest fruits
of time shall reap.
Some day without a
trumpet's call,
This news shall
o'er the earth be blown:
The heritage comes
back to all;
The myriad
monarchs take their own.
- Thomas Wentworth
Higginson
Grimly
the same spirit looks into the law of Property, and accuses men of
driving a trade in the great boundless Providence which had given the
air, the water, and the land to men to use and not to fence in and
monopolize. ("The Times.") I
cannot occupy the bleakest crag of the White Hills or the Allegheny
Range, but some man or corporation steps up to me to show me that it is
his. ("The Conservative.") Touch
any wood, or field, or house lot on your peril; but you may come and
work in ours for us, and we will give you a piece of bread. ("The
Conservative.") Of
course, whilst another man has no land, my title to mine, your title to
yours, is at once vitiated. ("Man the
Reformer.")
- Ralph Waldo Emerson
Properly
speaking, the land belongs to these two: To the Almighty God; and to
all his Children of Men that have ever worked well on it, or that shall
ever work well on it. No generation of men can or could, with never
such solemnity and effort, sell Land on any other principle: it is not
the property of any generation.
- Thomas Carlyle, in
"Past and Present,"
Book III, Chapter VIII.
To
any plain understanding the right of property is very simple. It is the
right of man to possess, enjoy, and transfer, the substance and use of
whatever he has himself created. This title is good against the world;
and it is the sole and only title by which a valid right of absolute
private property can possibly vest. But no man can plead any such title
to a right of property in the substance of the soil.
- James Fintan Lalor, in "The
Irish Felon," July 8, 1848.
It is easy to persuade the masses that the good things of this
world are unjustly divided - especially when it happens to be the
exact truth.
- Froude's "Caesar."
To
affirm that a man can rightfully claim exclusive ownership in his own
labor when embodied in material things, is to deny that any one can
rightfully claim exclusive ownership in land. -("Progress
and Poverty," Book VII, Ch. I.)
So far from the recognition of private property in land being necessary
to the proper use of land, the contrary is the case. Treating land as
private property stands in the way of its proper use. Were land treated
as public property it would be used and improved as soon as there was
need for its use or improvement, but being treated as private property,
the individual owner is permitted to prevent others from using or
improving what he cannot or will not use or improve himself.
-(Same, Book VIII, Ch. I.) We
should satisfy the law of justice, we should meet all economic
requirements, by at one stroke abolishing all private titles, declaring
all land public property, and letting it out to the highest bidders in
lots to suit, under such conditions as would sacredly guard the private
right to improvements.... But such a plan, though perfectly feasible,
does not seem to me the best. Or rather I propose to accomplish the
same thing in a simpler, easier, and quieter way, than that of formally
confiscating all the land and formally letting it out to the highest
bidders.... We already take some rent in taxation. We have only to make
some changes in our modes of taxation to take it all. What I,
therefore, propose... is - to appropriate rent by taxation.... Now,
inasmuch as the taxation of rent, or land values, must necessarily be
increased just as we abolish other taxes, we may put the proposition
into practical form by proposing - to
abolish all taxation save that upon land values.
(Same, Book VIII, Ch. II.)
- Henry George
Hither,
ye blind, from your futile banding!
Know the rights
and the rights are won.
Wrong shall die
with the understanding,
One truth clear,
and the work is done.
Nature is higher
than Progress or Knowledge
Whose need is
ninety enslaved for ten.
My word shall
stand against mart and college:
The planet belongs
to its living men!
- "Liberty," by John
Boyle O'Reilly
|
Saving Communities
Bringing
prosperity through freedom, equality, local
autonomy and respect for the commons.
|
The Ethics of Democracy
by Louis F. Post
Part 5,
Politico-Economic Principles
Chapter 4, The Wages System
IN any general classification of economic phenomena, the
returns which one exacts and receives for his work would be considered
as his wages, no matter whether he exacts and receives them by making
and selling things, or by hiring out to an employer. Even the things he
makes himself and consumes himself go into the category of wages. In
other words, wages are the returns for work. But there is a narrow use
of the term, in vogue especially with business men, but common also
with socialists, which restricts its meaning to the stipends that
mechanics and unskilled laborers receive of employers. Clerks do not
get "wages"; they get "salaries." Employers do not get "wages"; they
get "profits." Professional men do not get "wages"; they get "fees."
But ordinary laborers who hire out to an employer, they get
"wages."
This looseness of nomenclature has been encouraged by the mystification
theories of political economy that have been running their course
through American universities, like the whooping cough or the measles
through a district school. The most prominent characteristics of these
mighty triflings with the human reason are infinite detail and slovenly
classification. They are often so absurd in those respects as far and
away to outdo old Polonius in his analysis of the drama into "tragedy,
comedy, history, pastoral, pastorical-comical, historical-pastoral,
tragical-historical, tragical-comical-historical-pastoral, scene
individable or poem unlimited."
This lack-method method of university "economics" tends to give
"scientific" sanction to the notion that the phenomenon of employer and
hired men, the hired men who get "wages" as distinguished from those
who get "salaries," "fees," etc., is different from the general
phenomena of the exchange of services in trade. The supposed difference
is usually distinguished by referring to that phenomenon as "the wages
system."
The plutocrat stubbornly clings to "the wages system" as something
good, while the socialist wishes to abolish it as an unmitigated evil.
Both see it, however, in the same way. They see it as Talmage and
Ingersoll saw religion, upside down; and like Talmage and Ingersoll
with inverted religion, one likes it and the other doesn't. According
to this economic concept, labor is a commodity. It is bought and sold
in the markets; and its price, like the prices of other commodities,
rises and falls with the fluctuations of demand and supply the demand
that affects labor price being demand of employers for wage workers,
and the supply being the supply of men willing to be hired.
To the socialist "the wages system" is a system of slavery, the wage
worker being forced by it to sell himself from period to period, for
life, in a market glutted with wage workers. To the captain of industry
it is a convenient system - he would not call it slavery, for he
doesn't like the word - of making "capital and labor friends, not
enemies," by bringing them into "voluntary" cooperation, like that of
the lamb and the lion when the lamb is within. To both it appears to be
a normal development of competitive industry, and in this view the
"economic" cult of the universities "scientifically" concurs.
That the industrial relations of employers and employed are now
regulated oppressively is true. That this system is a system of slavery
is equally so. The labor market of the present time is a veritable
slave mart. Labor, in the existing industrial regime, is nothing but a
commodity. The man himself is sold. Nor is this shocking condition
modified by the fact that he is sold by himself. It is all the more
shocking that men should be forced by circumstances to beg some one to
buy them. Under this "wages system," let it be noted also, the buyer
contracts none of the personal obligations of the slave master. He pays
the wage-slave the cost of his poor "keep," and there his
responsibility ends.
But it is one thing to recognize the "wages system" as an industrial
phenomenon of the existing order of things (the existing disorder is a
better phrase), and quite another to conclude that it is a system in
the sense of being a normal regulation of the industrial relations of
employer and employed in a competitive social order. Normally the
"wages system" as it exists is utterly foreign to the principle of free
competition. It is not a product of normal competition; it is a social
disease developed from strangulated competition.
All this may be readily perceived upon a commonsense investigation. It
is obscure only to minds that are over-stored with detail and
over-tutored in "scientific" methods of economic classification.
Clearness of analysis, not profundity of learning nor wealth of
statistical information, is the requisite for an examination into the
subject. By that method of examination it may be plainly seen that the
"wages system," as we experience it now, is a painfully distorted image
of what would under free competition be one of the beneficial phenomena
of trade.
For understanding the nature of the "wages system," industrial history
does not furnish the best material. Of the usefulness
of industrial history as a side light there need be no
question. But it is from a consideration of the laws of human nature as
we perceive them in operation in ourselves and in our neighbors, that
the truest explanation of the "wages system" is to be had. We do know
in a general way how men in general will act under given circumstances
of a general kind. We do not know in a particular way what particular
men will do under given circumstances of a particular kind. History
cannot tell us; neither can statistics. The crudest generalizations
from human nature as to the probabilities of human conduct in given
circumstances are much more likely to be true than the most expert
generalizations from historical or statistical data.
We know, for example, or we can know if we reason about the familiar
characteristics of human nature, what men in general would do as to
accepting or rejecting wages, provided they were living in the fullest
freedom that the laws of external nature permit. Let us, then, assume
for the starting point of an inquiry into the wages system that men are
living in such freedom. In other words, let us imagine - not as
romancers imagine plots and incidents, but as mathematicians imagine
axioms - what the wages system would be in healthy industrial
conditions. In that way alone can we safely determine whether the wages
system is essentially a plundering device, or a normal manifestation of
industrial life, naturally beneficent but perverted by industrial
disease.
In the fullest conceivable freedom men would have to work. Natural laws
do not permit them to live without eating, and unless they work they
cannot eat. This is manifestly true of men in the sense of mankind, or
as a whole. Individual men may eat without working; but if they do, it
is only because other men work without a full equivalent. And other men
will not ordinarily do that, unless coerced. In the absence of
coercion, then, every man must work in order to live.
It is instinctive with men, however, to do the least work for the
greatest result. They naturally seek the best living in the easiest
way. That is the incentive to labor-saving invention. But for this
human instinct none of the devices for the lessening of human effort
and the enhanced production of human satisfactions would be utilized.
One of the devices for this purpose, in fact the all inclusive device,
since every other springs from it, is trade.
No individual could with his own direct labor supply his own wants. He
could neither feed himself, nor clothe himself, nor house himself in a
civilized way, if he were obliged to make all his own food and clothing
and shelter. But by acquiring skill in making one kind of commodity he
may by means of trade swap the particular commodities that he makes,
for those that he wants. When he does this in freedom, the things that
each receives in the trade are as truly his earnings, economically and
morally, as if he had made them himself.
Here, then, is a system which springs up naturally, not merely as a
historical evolution, but as a spontaneous expression of human powers
of production acting under the impulse of human desires to get the most
with the least effort. Industrial history records the process of
development with more or less accuracy, but the nature of the
phenomenon may be better understood by logical analysis than from
historical data. This system is natural industrial cooperation
generated and maintained by trade. Every trade is a private contract
between two individuals, and the myriads of such trades, interdependent
like the links of chain armor, produce, when made in freedom, a
perfection of cooperation to which no premeditated cooperative scheme
could approximate.
If we suppose that trade would naturally first be manifest in bartering
labor products - the actual order of development is neither known
historically nor really important philosophically - we can understand
that fluctuations in demand for particular products would require every
producer to be a business man in the sense of keeping himself well
informed regarding the multifarious variations of demand and supply.
But this would divert his energy from direct production. He could not
acquire business skill except at the expense of skill in his primary
calling; and that being uneconomical, the instinct we have already
described - that instinct which impels men to satisfy their desires
with the least exertion - would lead some producers to cultivate
business skill at the expense of skill of other kinds, and to
contribute to the sum of cooperative energies by relieving producers of
the necessity of watching for trading opportunities. Men in this new
occupation would buy and sell as middlemen. They would be in a sense
speculators in labor products, buying when and where demand was low and
selling when and where it was higher. The service they would render
would be to save the expenditure by original producers of their
energies in the processes of trading. And this would be a genuine
service; else original producers, being free from coercion, would have
nothing to do with the middleman. They would themselves superintend the
processes of trading, if, all things considered, they could do so
advantageously. And if middlemen made excessive profits, other
producers, being free from coercion, would compete until the incomes of
middlemen had been reduced to the level of incomes for original
production requiring equal skill and effort.
So much is obvious. To understand human nature in its more general
manifestations is to perceive that in the circumstances supposed men
would act in the manner indicated. If an industrial history were to
describe any considerable community of free men as having in such
circumstances habitually acted essentially otherwise, we should all
unhesitatingly say, So much the worse for that industrial history.
Every sane man would promptly reject such a history as manifestly a
romance, and rest his conclusions upon his conviction that human
nature, like mathematical axioms, is the same everywhere and at all
times.
We are now prepared to see how a legitimate wages system, the genuine
and useful system of which the one we are familiar with is the
distorted image, may develop.
As production, facilitated by trade, divides and subdivides and
consequently becomes more complex, men find it profitable to devote
their labor to the making of only parts of commodities. To borrow an
illustration from modern industry, one man does nothing but make shoe
soles. If all were free, this would not be done unless those who did it
found it advantageous to themselves. Coercion, it must be understood,
is excluded from consideration at present.
Or, we may refer to such industries as house building or ship building.
No individual would be able alone to build a house or a ship. He must
cooperate with others. With some, those who work with him upon the
house or the ship itself, he cooperates directly and consciously; but
with by far the larger number he cooperates indirectly and
unconsciously through trade. Suppose that a dozen house builders wish
to build each of them a house. Since they cannot themselves do all the
work that is involved in house building, they must trade the products
of their labor, through the intricate network of commerce, with all the
thousands of unknown laborers in a multiplicity of occupations who
cooperate with them. If the house builders have no accumulated
products, or credit acquired in the form of money or otherwise for
products they have previously produced, then, either to middlemen, or
directly to the producers of material, they must "mortgage," to use a
colloquialism, a share in the houses they are about to build; and,
having built these houses, they will own the houses in proportion to
their several contributions of labor, subject to the shares of the
producers of the materials. This would be natural cooperation in house
building. But it would be exceedingly complex cooperation were it not
for the middlemen who accumulate, by buying from the thousands of
miscellaneous producers, the materials and tools which the immediate
builders must have.
Even with these middlemen as labor-savers, for such they are, the dozen
builders might not find their partnership method the most satisfactory.
One might want a house, and therefore be willing to join the other
eleven in building twelve houses, each to take one for his work. But if
the others did not want houses, except to trade them for something
else, they would hesitate about going into the enterprise unless they
were assured of trading opportunities. At this point the employer, as
we call him in the distorted "wages system" of our time, would step in
to correlate all the house-producing forces and thereby promote the
erection and distribution of those twelve houses.
He would buy the houses in advance of their erection. That is, he would
say to the dozen house-builders: "Gentlemen, I will marshal the
material for the projected houses, and will pay you so much apiece for
them as compensation for your work after it is done; or I will pay you
so much weekly as you proceed with the work. If I pay you at the end of
the job, I shall pay you more than if I pay you from week to week as
the work goes on. Let us agree together." The builders, being' free to
accept or reject these terms, and under no fear of poverty if they
decline, will decide, considering similar offers from other middlemen,
whether to accept the offer; and, if they do accept, whether or not to
take the higher pay for the houses when finished or the lower pay in
weekly wages. They will do in the matter what seems most profitable to
themselves.
Suppose they take the weekly wages, preferring its benefits and
certainties to the greater benefits but lesser certainty and longer
delay of payment at the end of the job. Then we have the wages system.
But what is it other than a fair and mutually beneficial mode of
cooperation?
These builders do not sell themselves. They discount the value of their
future work for the sake of an immediate trade of what they make for
what they want. At the end the houses will have been produced by
cooperation, by a fair partnership arrangement, as truly as if it had
been a partnership in form. The only difference is that one of the
partners buys up the interest of the others in advance, in a free
contract which is as beneficial to them as to him. Though he gets
something which they by trading the houses themselves might get, yet he
does work in effecting the trades, which but for him they would have to
drop house building to attend to. In other words, he earns what he
gets, and they lose nothing that they earn.
Reduced to the last analysis, this wages system is a system under which
employer and employes are free cooperators, all sharing in the final
result, namely, those things for which the product is traded. The
employer's share is compensation for his work in effecting the trades
that marshal the materials, for his work in superintending the
production, and for his work in trading the product; while the shares
of the employes are compensation for their work in putting the
materials together, without being troubled either to marshal the
materials or to trade the final product.
And these shares must be mutually satisfactory, for in free conditions
neither party to the hiring contract need allow the other to oppress
him. Competition bearing not in only one direction, but, like the
pressure of the air, bearing with equal force in all directions,
maintains an equilibrium of compensation for every worker at the point
of his earnings. The wages system, then, in free conditions, is a mode
of cooperation which adjusts itself to the satisfaction of all the
cooperators by their mutual consent.
Under that natural wages system hired laborers are not commodities.
They remain partners or cooperators in production, discounting their
demands, upon satisfactory terms, in return for exemption from certain
kinds of necessary labor. But the fairness and usefulness of this
system depend upon the freedom of its environment.
In coercive conditions this natural and most useful mode of dividing
labor and distributing its proceeds is degraded into a distorted image
of the true wages system. Socialists denounce this image, this spurious
"wages system," as a species of slavery. And they are right. When
social institutions perpetuate obstructions to trade and foster the
monopoly of natural opportunities for labor, so that workmen sell their
labor in a glutted market because they cannot utilize it otherwise,
then the relation of employer and employe ceases to be a relationship
of free cooperators and becomes in greater or less degree a
relationship of master and slave. It is evident, however, that the seat
of the injustice is not the wages system. It is the effect upon the
wages system of unfree conditions.
By promoting the monopoly of natural opportunities for production and
trade - the soil and the mine, factory and store sites, rights of way
for transportation, and the various other facilities which nature
provides for labor, and which are more or less included in those
enumerated - and by taxing labor in every direction in which it turns
for purposes of production, we have generated in place of free
competition a jug-handled competition, a competition that is all
one-sided. Employers and employes do not contract upon even ground. The
employer offers his own terms, and the employe must either accept or
starve. Natural opportunities being closed by private monopoly, and
production and trade being checked by taxation upon enterprise and
thrift, the supply of labor tends constantly to outrun the effective
demand for labor, and so to maintain a glutted "labor market."
Competition in these circumstances is like air pressure in only one
direction. Laborers are subject to the pressure of competition on their
side, but are not protected in equal degree by the pressure of
competition on the other. The equilibrium is thereby disturbed, and the
wages system becomes distorted in consequence into the shape that
incenses the socialist and pleases the captain of industry.
Labor has no proper quarrel with the natural wages system which a
discriminating examination into the subject discovers. That system is
one of the useful adjustments of cooperative production. To make war
upon it is to distract attention and to divert reformatory energy from
the real evil that turns this useful adjustment into an engine of
oppression. We cannot destroy the wages system without making men over
again, or putting them into governmental strait jackets. We can, if we
will, destroy the monopolies which so disturb the competitive
equilibrium as to reduce laborers to the condition of dependent and
desperate hunters for work, and to make freedom of contract between
employer and employe a dismal mockery. With monopolies destroyed,
freedom of contract would be restored and the "wages system" would no
longer be oppressive.
|
Navigation
We Provide
How You Can Help
- Research
- Outreach
- Transcribing Documents
- Donating Money
- Training for Responsibility
Our Constituents
- Public Officials
- Small Businesses
- Family Farms
- Organic Farms
- Vegetarians
- Labor
- Real Estate Leaders
- Innovative Land Speculators
- Homeowners
- Tenants
- Ethnic
Minorities
- Ideological Groups
Fundamental Principles
- Decentralism and Freedom
- Focusing on Local Reform
- Government as Referee
- Government as Public Servant
- Earth as a Commons
- Money as a Common Medium
- Property Derives from Labor
Derivative Issues
- Wealth Concentration
- Corruption
- Bureaucracy
- Authorities
- Privatization
- Centralization
- Globalization and Trade
- Economic Stagnation
- Boom-Bust Cycles
- Development Subsidies
- Sprawl
- Gentrification
- Pollution and Depletion
- Public Services
- Transportation
- Education
- Health Care
- Retirement
- Wages
- Zoning
- Parks
- Shared Services
Blinding Misconceptions
- Orwellian Economics
- Corporate Efficiency
- Democracy vs. Elections
- Big Government Solutions
- Founding Fathers
- Politics of Fear
- Politics of Least Resistance
- Radical vs. Militant
- Left vs. Right
- Common vs. Collective
- Analysis vs. Vilification
- Influence vs. Power
|